segunda-feira, 23 de julho de 2012

Students Confront Contraceptive Establishment With "1Flesh" Website - by Elizabeth Crnkovich

I PRI

“We want sexy back!” This is the cry of today's generation, raised in a sex-drenched culture that threatens to empty relationships between the sexes of all love, meaning and romance. 

A network of university students from around the country, brought together by Marc Barnes, knew that human sexuality was intended to be something beautiful, and that it deserved greater respect and appreciation in the world today. They decided that it was high time that someone told the truth about sex, and exposed the root of today's widespread sexual dissatisfaction. 

So it was that in May of this year, these students launched a website entitled: “1Flesh: The Revolt Against Contraception in Marriage.” They described their effort as “A grassroots movement in opposition to the use of artificial contraception, dedicated to bringing great sex to the entire universe.” 

The sexual revolution of the last generation has left a legacy of broken lives and broken hearts for all to see. Young people do not want to make the same mistakes as their parents and older siblings. They want to be seen as persons, not sex objects. They want romance, not the humdrum boredom of loveless sex. They want monogamy, not the multiple partners that leads to STDs. Today's generation is searching to regain what their parents lost. 

1Flesh believes that things went wrong when contraception entered marriage. Not only is contraception not the answer, they believe that it is a root cause of all our present ills. It lessens the bond of sexual union, dulls its unifying nature, and causes many health problems that could be avoided if couples used natural family planning. This is where 1Flesh takes a stand against society's current practices. 

The goal of 1Flesh is “to spread words of rebellion; that sex should be awesome and saved until marriage, that pregnancy can be justly avoided without harmful chemicals, and that love is worth fighting for.” 

The website contains a vast array of images, videos, testimonies, data, and statistics all arguing against the use of artificial birth control and in favor of what it likes to call “100% organic sex.” It also introduces readers to a natural and healthy means of fertility regulation, namely, Natural Family Planning. It explains the benefits of several different NFP methods, such as The Creighton Model Fertiltycare System and The Billings Ovulation Method, in detail. 

And that’s not all. The website is chock full of information about the emotional, physical, and environmental dangers of artificial birth control, all told with flashy and attention-grabbing visuals that I found both informative and entertaining. 

In their own words, 1Flesh strives “to inform women of the risks of birth control pills, to call out pharmaceutical companies for their life-endangering, false and manipulating advertising of the drugs, and to promote the concept that women can understand and work with their own fertility instead of relying on pharmaceutical companies.” 

I was impressed by the detailed explanations of how men and women are harmed emotionally and physically by the use of contraceptives such as the pill and condoms. I was particularly touched by testimonies from former contraception users, many of whom now rely upon NFP, about how they have found physical and emotional health again after experiencing the negative impact of contraceptives in their lives. 

The website has received a great deal of publicity since it went online in May, and Marc Barnes has been interviewed by the Huffington Post and other media outlets. As you might expect, the site has also received more than its share of attacks. 

But Marc and his collaborators are hanging in there, fighting the good fight. They saw the need, heard the cries, saw the demand, and so took action. We at PRI salute them!

Nueva hipótesis sobre uno de los grandes misterios del Nuevo Testamento

In Religión en Libertad

Durante siglos, los exégetas y estudiosos de las Sagradas Escrituras se han tropezado con un misterio sin aparente solución: los Evangelios sinópticos (San Mateo, San Marcos y San Lucas) incluyen un relato de la institución de la Eucaristía, y sin embargo el de San Juan no, a pesar de que dedica cinco capítulos -mucho más que los otros evangelistas- a la Última Cena y al sermón de Nuestro Señor en ella.

Ahora parece que la solución ha sido encontrada o, al menos, una hipótesis verosímil. Sintetiza 35 años de estudios de monseñor Anthony La Femina, canonista y teólogo que trabajó durante años en el Pontificio Consejo para la Familia, y que ha escrito un libro, Eucharist and Covenant in John’s Last Supper Account [Eucaristía y Alianza en el relato de Juan de la Última Cena], reseñado por National Catholic Register. La legitimidad de la hipótesis viene avalada por el prólogo que presta a la obra el cardenal Raymond Burke, prefecto del Tribunal Supremo de la Signatura Apostólica y uno de los más leales representantes de la "línea Benedicto XVI" en la Curia.

La tesis de La Femina es que también San Juan relata la institución de la Eucaristía, pero de forma analógica en la acción de Jesús de lavar los pies a los apóstoles. San Juan "utiliza el recurso de la analogía para transmitir verdades sobre la Eucaristía que no son evidentes en otros relatos de la Última Cena", afirma.

Para demostrar este aserto recurre a un estudio filológico griego y hebreo y a las conclusiones de otros estudios que han precedido al suyo, sobre el sentido teológico de las ceremonias de alianza de Dios con su pueblo.

Según La Femina, el lavatorio incluye en el Evangelio de San Juan idénticas circunstancias, atributos y efectos que la Eucaristía en los sinópticos, incluida la orden de repetir la acción, signo de la muerte de Jesús, así como el entorno físico y teológico, el orden de los hechos y la secuencia de las palabras.

En su opinión, todo el relato de San Juan de la Última Cena remite a las tradiciones del Antiguo Testamento para el establecimiento de una alianza y eran reconocibles por los contemporáneos de Jesús. La Femina estudia esa correspondencia versículo a versículo.

Hay una continuidad, pues, entre la Antigua Alianza y la Nueva Alianza, y en ese contexto el mandamiento nuevo ("amaos los unos a los otros como yo os he amado") tiene una implicación eucarística directa: "Además de ser apostólico, el mandamiento nuevo es esencialmente eucarístico: no sólo supone la alianza cristiana con el Padre en la vida y actividad del Hijo, sino también la unión con la vida y actividad de Jesús en el seno del sacrificio eucarístico", concluye La Femina.

La idea de que, mediante el lavatorio de pies, San Juan pretende iluminar la naturaleza de la Nueva Alianza instituida por la Eucaristía, y lo que esto signfica (a través del mandamiento del amor) para todos los cristianos, es "sorprendente", subraya la editorial dominica que ha publicado el libro; es "atractiva e innovadora, pero absolutamente compatible con la doctrina católica", según el prestigioso teólogo dominico Aidan Nichols, profesor en Oxford y Cambridge y autor en 1988 de un estudio sobre la teología de Joseph Ratzinger; y es "un regalo para la Iglesia", en palabras
del cardenal Burke. Toda una invitación para la reflexión escriturística y teológica de los especialistas.

Ovo de crocodilo - por João César das Neves

In DN

Ficamos sempre impressionados ao considerar a incapacidade de sociedades antigas em antecipar o que mais as afectaria. Parece incrível que pessoas inteligentes se tenham deixado cair em horrores para nós tão evidentes. Pensando assim vamos, como eles, dirigindo-nos inconscientemente para as próximas catástrofes.

Não é preciso recuar à queda do império romano ou ao fim de Constantinopla. Um dos mistérios da história é a inépcia da brilhante sociedade iluminista em precaver os horrores seguintes, com a sangrenta Revolução Francesa e o cruel império napoleónico. Porque foram tão cegos alguns dos mais profundos espíritos da nossa civilização? Também é sumamente incongruente que a sofisticada Alemanha do início do século XX falhasse no pressentimento da barbaridade nazi que germinava no seu seio. Em 1977, Ingmar Bergman usou a comparação de O Ovo da Serpente para manifestar este espanto. Como não viram, através da casca translúcida, o réptil em formação?

A conclusão desta meditação não deve ser que algo falhava nessa elevação intelectual ou que os movimentos da História escapam até aos génios. Isso deve motivar-nos a procurar as múltiplas sementes de abominação que brotam hoje, como sempre. Que tendências nos podem conduzir ao horror? As histórias revelam que tais venenos raramente estão entre aqueles que a sociedade identifica.

Dizer que a nossa época se encaminha para o cataclismo não é propriamente grande novidade. Não temos a complacência do Trianon ou Weimar. Desde a bomba atómica que a humanidade encara a extinção, e a recente crise financeira levou ao paroxismo a sensação de fim de regime. Mas também aqui as nossas preocupações escondem-nos a verdadeira ameaça. Não é a falência do Lehman Brothers ou o programa nuclear iraniano que nos arruinarão. O mal não está nas exigências de Angela Merkel ou na concorrência com a China. Apesar de graves, esses são detalhes laterais como o Caso do Colar de 1785. A serpente está noutro ovo, que teimamos em não olhar à transparência.

Aquilo que os nossos descendentes não conseguirão compreender é a nossa inacreditável ligeireza e inoperância perante factos devastadores, que subjazem a tudo o mais: "No primeiro semestre deste ano, nasceram menos quatro mil bebés do que no mesmo período de 2011. Se a tendência de decréscimo se mantiver, 2012 poderá ficar para a história como o ano em que os nascimentos não chegaram aos 90 mil, algo que nunca aconteceu desde que há registos" (DN, 5/Julho). Sem portugueses não há economia, consumo, emprego, ensino, justiça, país. Com a atenção centrada no défice, desemprego, ou pior, nas tricas do momento, Portugal resvala para a decadência perante a apatia generalizada.

Somos um dos países do mundo com menor taxa de fertilidade, muito inferior à dos nossos parceiros, aliás também entre os mais estéreis. Essas sociedades desenvolvidas há muito identificaram o problema e criaram políticas resolutas para o enfrentar, com sucessos muito díspares. Em Portugal a medida recente neste campo é o subsidiação do aborto, que aliás é a única área da Saúde onde os cortes financeiros não têm efeito.

Pior, neste tema, ao contrário dos casos históricos, estamos em violação aberta dos mais elementares princípios da civilização. Luís XVI ou Von Hindenburg podiam dizer que a sua boçalidade seguia os cânones recebidos. Nós, ao apregoarmos o aborto como direito, contrariamos séculos de civilização. Que a atrocidade de arrancar o embrião do seio da sua mãe, prática recusada por toda as sociedades cultas, seja por nós promovida pelo Estado será incompreensível aos nossos poucos descendentes.

Nos raros casos em que o tema surge nas conversas, atribui-se a redução da natalidade à crise e ao desemprego, sem notar a incongruência de serem os pobres os mais férteis. Insiste-se na muralha de falácias que tenta esconder a multidão de pequenos cadáveres. Após novo gole de café, o debate regressa às intrigas da semana. É perfeito o paralelo com Versalhes em 1789. Porque o ovo de crocodilo é opaco.

domingo, 22 de julho de 2012

The road from atheism - by Edward Feser


As most of my readers probably know, I was an atheist for about a decade -- roughly the 1990s, give or take.  Occasionally I am asked how I came to reject atheism.  I briefly addressed this in The Last Superstition.  A longer answer, which I offer here, requires an account of the atheism I came to reject.

I was brought up Catholic, but lost whatever I had of the Faith by the time I was about 13 or 14.  Hearing, from a non-Catholic relative, some of the stock anti-Catholic arguments for the first time -- “That isn’t in the Bible!”, “This came from paganism!”, “Here’s what they did to people in the Middle Ages!”, etc. -- I was mesmerized, and convinced, seemingly for good.  Sola scriptura-based arguments are extremely impressive, until you come to realize that their basic premise -- sola scriptura itself -- has absolutely nothing to be said for it.  Unfortunately it takes some people, like my younger self, a long time to see that.  Such arguments can survive even the complete loss of religious belief, the anti-Catholic ghost that carries on beyond the death of the Protestant body, haunting the atheist who finds himself sounding like Martin Luther when debating his papist friends. 
But I was still a theist for a time, though that wouldn’t survive my undergrad years.  Kierkegaard was my first real philosophical passion, and his individualistic brand of religiosity greatly appealed to me.  But the individualistic irreligion of Nietzsche would come to appeal to me more, and for a time he was my hero, with Walter Kaufmann a close second.  (I still confess an affection for Kaufmann.  Nietzsche, not so much.)  Analytic philosophy would, before long, bring my youthful atheism down to earth.  For the young Nietzschean the loss of religion is a grand, civilizational crisis, and calls for an equally grand response on the part of a grand individual like himself.  For the skeptical analytic philosopher it’s just a matter of rejecting some bad arguments, something one does quickly and early in one’s philosophical education before getting on to the really interesting stuff.  And that became my “settled” atheist position while in grad school.  Atheism was like belief in a spherical earth -- something everyone in possession of the relevant facts knows to be true, and therefore not worth getting too worked up over or devoting too much philosophical attention to.

But it takes some reading and thinking to get to that point.  Kaufmann’s books were among my favorites, serious as they were on the “existential” side of disbelief without the ultimately impractical pomposity of Nietzsche.  Naturally I took it for granted that Hume, Kant, et al. had identified the main problems with the traditional proofs of God’s existence long ago.  On issues of concern to a contemporary analytic philosopher, J. L. Mackie was the man, and I regarded his book The Miracle of Theism as a solid piece of philosophical work.  I still do.  I later came to realize that he doesn’t get Aquinas or some other things right.  (I discuss what he says about Aquinas in Aquinas.)  But the book is intellectually serious, which is more than can be said for anything written by a “New Atheist.”  Antony Flew’s challenge to the intelligibility of various religious assertions may have seemed like dated “ordinary language” philosophy to some, but I was convinced there was something to it.  Kai Nielsen was the “go to” guy on issues of morality and religion.  Michael Martin’s Atheism: A Philosophical Justification was a doorstop of a book, and a useful compendium of arguments.  I used to wonder with a little embarrassment whether my landlord, who was religious but a nice guy, could see that big word “ATHEISM” on its spine -- sitting there sort of like a middle finger on the bookshelf behind me -- when he’d come to collect the rent.  But if so he never raised an eyebrow or said a word about it.

The argument from evil was never the main rationale for my atheism; indeed, the problem of suffering has only gotten really interesting to me since I returned to the Catholic Church.  (Not because the existence of suffering poses a challenge to the truth of classical theism -- for reasons I’ve given elsewhere, I think it poses no such challenge at all -- but because the role various specific instances of suffering actually play in divine providence is often really quite mysterious.)  To be sure, like any other atheist I might have cited the problem of suffering when rattling off the reasons why theism couldn’t be true, but it wasn’t what primarily impressed me philosophically.  What really impressed me was the evidentialist challenge to religious belief.  If God really exists there should be solid arguments to that effect, and there just aren’t, or so I then supposed.  Indeed, that there were no such arguments seemed to me something which would itself be an instance of evil if God existed, and this was an aspect of the problem of evil that seemed really novel and interesting.  

I see from a look at my old school papers that I was expressing this idea in a couple of essays written for different courses in 1992.  (I think that when J. L. Schellenberg’s book Divine Hiddenness and Human Reason appeared in 1993 I was both gratified that someone was saying something to that effect in print, and annoyed that it wasn’t me.)  Attempts to sidestep the evidentialist challenge, like Alvin Plantinga’s, did not convince me, and still don’t.  My Master’s thesis was a defense of “evidentialism” against critics like Plantinga.  I haven’t read it in years, but I imagine that, apart from its atheism and a detail here or there, I’d still agree with it.  

I was also greatly impressed by the sheer implausibility of attributing humanlike characteristics to something as rarefied as the cause of the world.  J. C. A. Gaskin’s The Quest for Eternity had a fascinating section on the question of whether a centre of consciousness could coherently be attributed to God, a problem I found compelling.  Moreover, the very idea of attributing moral virtues (or for that matter moral vices) to God seemed to make no sense, given that the conditions that made talk of kindness, courage, etc. intelligible in human life could not apply to Him.  Even if something otherwise like God did exist, I thought, He would be “beyond good and evil” -- He would not be the sort of thing one could attribute moral characteristics to, and thus wouldn’t be the God of Judaism, Christianity, and Islam.  (Richard Swinburne’s attempt to show otherwise did not work, as I argued in another school paper.)  The Euthyphro problem, which also had a big impact on me, only reinforced the conclusion that you couldn’t tie morality to God in the way that (as I then assumed) the monotheistic religions required.

Those were, I think, the main components of my mature atheism: the conviction that theists could neither meet nor evade the evidentialist challenge; and the view that there could be, in any event, no coherent notion of a cause of the world with the relevant humanlike attributes.  What is remarkable is how much of the basis I then had for these judgments I still find compelling.  As I would come to realize only years later, the conception of God I then found so implausible was essentially a modern, parochial, and overly anthropomorphic “theistic personalist” conception, and not the classical theism to which the greatest theistic philosophers had always been committed.  And as my longtime readers know, I still find theistic personalism objectionable.  The fideism that I found (and still find) so appalling was, as I would also come to see only later, no part of the mainstream classical theist tradition either.  And while the stock objections raised by atheists against the traditional arguments for God’s existence are often aimed at caricatures, some of them do have at least some force against some of the arguments of modern philosophers of religion.  But they do not have force against the key arguments of the classical theist tradition.

It is this classical tradition -- the tradition of Aristotelians, Neo-Platonists, and Thomists and other Scholastics -- that I had little knowledge of then.  To be sure, I had read the usual selections from Plato, Aristotle, Aquinas and Anselm that pretty much every philosophy student reads -- several of Plato’s dialogues, the Five Ways, chapter 2 of the Proslogium, and so forth.  Indeed, I read a lot more than that.  I’d read the entire Proslogium of Anselm, as well as the Monologium, the Cur Deus Homo, and the exchange with Gaunilo, early in my undergraduate years.  I’d read Aquinas’s De Ente et Essentia and De Principiis Naturae, big chunks of Plotinus’s Enneads, Athanasius’s On the Incarnation, Augustine’s Concerning the Teacher, and Bonaventure’s The Mind’s Road to God.  I’d read Russell’s History of Western Philosophy -- hardly an unbiased source, to be sure -- but also a bit of Gilson.  All while becoming an atheist during my undergrad years.  And I still didn’t understand the classical tradition.

Why not?  Because to read something is not necessarily to understand it.  Partly, of course, because when you’re young, you always understand less than you think you do.  But mainly because, to understand someone, it’s not enough to sit there tapping your foot while he talks.  You’ve got to listen, rather than merely waiting for a pause so that you can insert the response you’d already formulated before he even opened his mouth.  And when you’re a young man who thinks he’s got the religious question all figured out, you’re in little mood to listen -- especially if you’ve fallen in love with one side of the question, the side that’s new and sexy because it’s not what you grew up believing.  Zeal of the deconverted, and all that.

You’re pretty much just going through the motions at that point.  And if, while in that mindset, what you’re reading from the other side are seemingly archaic works, written in a forbidding jargon, presenting arguments and ideas no one defends anymore (or at least no one in the “mainstream”), your understanding is bound to be superficial and inaccurate.  You’ll take whatever happens to strike you as the main themes, read into them what you’re familiar with from modern writers, and ignore the unfamiliar bits as irrelevant.  “This part sounds like what Leibniz or Plantinga says, but Hume and Mackie already showed what’s wrong with that; I don’t even know what the hell this other part means, but no one today seems to be saying that sort of thing anyway, so who cares…”  Read it, read into it, dismiss it, move on.  How far can you go wrong?

Very, very far.   It took me the better part of a decade to see that, and what prepared the way were some developments in my philosophical thinking that seemingly had nothing to do with religion.  The first of them had to do instead with the philosophy of language and logic.  Late in my undergrad years at Cal State Fullerton I took a seminar in logic and language in which the theme was the relationship between sentences and what they express.  (Propositions?  Meanings?  Thoughts?  That’s the question.)  Similar themes would be treated in courses I took in grad school, at first at Claremont and later at UC Santa Barbara.  Certain arguments stood out.  There was Alonzo Church’s translation argument, and, above all, Frege’s wonderful essay “The Thought.”  Outside of class I discovered Karl Popper’s World 3 concept, and the work of Jerrold Katz.  The upshot of these arguments was that the propositional content of sentences could not be reduced to or otherwise explained in terms of the utterances of sentences themselves, or behavioral dispositions, or psychological states, or conventions, or functions from possible worlds, or anything else a materialist might be willing to countenance.  As the arguments sank in over the course of months and years, I came to see that existing naturalistic accounts of language and meaning were no good.  

Not that that led me to give up naturalism, at least not initially.  A more nuanced, skeptical naturalism was my preferred approach -- what else was there, right?  My studies in the philosophy of mind reinforced this tendency.  At first, and like so many undergraduate philosophy majors, I took the materialist line for granted.  Mental activity was just brain activity.  What could be more obvious?  But reading John Searle’s The Rediscovery of the Mind destroyed this illusion, and convinced me that the standard materialist theories were all hopeless.  That Searle was himself a naturalist no doubt made this easier to accept.  Indeed, Searle became another hero of mine.  He was smart, funny, gave perfectly organized public lectures on complex topics without notes, and said whatever he thought whether or not it was fashionable.  And he wrote so beautifully, eschewing the needless formalisms that give a veneer of pseudo-rigor and “professionalism” to the writings of too many analytic philosophers.  “That is how I want to write!” I decided.  

Brilliant as he was as a critic, though, Searle’s own approach to the mind-body problem -- “biological naturalism” -- never convinced me.  It struck me (and seemingly everyone else but Searle himself) as a riff on property dualism.  But there was another major influence on my thinking in the philosophy of mind in those days, Michael Lockwood’s fascinating book Mind, Brain and the Quantum.  Lockwood was also a naturalist of sorts, and yet he too was critical of some of the standard materialist moves.  Most importantly, though, Lockwood’s book introduced me to Bertrand Russell’s later views on these issues, which would have a major influence on my thinking ever afterward.  Russell emphasized that physics really gives us very little knowledge of the material world.  In particular, it gives us knowledge of its abstract structure, of what can be captured in equations and the like.  But it gives us no knowledge of the intrinsic nature of matter, of the concrete reality that fleshes out the abstract structure.  Introspection, by contrast, gives us direct knowledge of our thoughts and experiences.  The upshot is that it is matter, and not mind, that is the really problematic side of the mind-body problem.  

This was truly revolutionary, and it reinforced the conclusion that contemporary materialism was shallow and dogmatic.  And that Lockwood and Russell were themselves naturalists made it once again easy to accept the message.  I got hold of whatever I could find on these neglected views of Russell’s -- Russell’s The Analysis of Matter and various essays and book chapters, Lockwood’s other writings on the topic, some terrific neglected essays by Grover Maxwell, some related arguments from John Foster and Howard Robinson.  David Chalmers and Galen Strawson were also starting to take an interest in Russell around that time.  But once again I found myself agreeing more with the criticisms than with the positive proposals.  Russell took the view that what fleshes out the structure described by physics were sense data (more or less what contemporary writers call qualia).  This might seem to entail a kind of panpsychism, the view that mental properties are everywhere in nature.  Russell avoided this bizarre result by arguing that sense data could exist apart from a conscious subject which was aware of them, and Lockwood took the same line.  I wasn’t convinced, and one of my earliest published articles was a criticism of Lockwood’s arguments on this subject (an article to which Lockwood very graciously replied).  Chalmers and Strawson, meanwhile, were flirting with the idea of just accepting the panpsychist tendency of Russell’s positive views, but that seemed crazy to me.

My preferred solution was to take the negative, critical side of the Russellian position -- the view that physics gives us knowledge only of the abstract structure of matter -- and push a similar line toward the mind itself.  All our knowledge, both of the external world described by physics and of the internal world of conscious experience and thought, was knowledge only of structure, of the relations between elements but not of their intrinsic nature.  I would discover that Rudolf Carnap had taken something in the ballpark of this position, but the main influence on my thinking here was, of all people, the economist and political philosopher F. A. Hayek.  The libertarianism I was then attracted to had already led me to take an interest in Hayek.  When I found out that he had written a book on the mind-body problem, and that it took a position like Russell’s only more radical, it seemed like kismet.  Hayek’s The Sensory Order and some of his related essays would come to be the major influences on my positive views.  

But they were inchoate, since Hayek was not a philosopher by profession.  That gave me something to do.  Working out Hayek’s position in a more systematic way than he had done would be the project of my doctoral dissertation, “Russell, Hayek, and the Mind-Body Problem.”  (Both here and in the earlier Master’s thesis link, by the way, Google books overstates the page count.  I wasn’t that long-winded!)  This was, to be sure, a very eccentric topic for a dissertation.  Russell’s views were marginal at the time, and are still not widely accepted.  Probably very few philosophers of mind even know who Hayek is, and fewer still care.  But I thought their views were both true and interesting, and that was that.  (If you want advice on how to climb the career ladder in academic philosophy, I’m not the guy to ask.  But you knew that already.)  

Spelling out the Hayekian position in a satisfactory way was very difficult.  Lockwood had presented Russell’s position as a kind of mind-brain identity theory in reverse: It’s not that the mind turns out to be the brain, but that the brain turns out to be the mind.  More precisely, visual and tactile perceptions of the brain of the sort a neurosurgeon might have do not tell us what the brain is really like, but present us only with a representation of the brain.  It is actually introspection of our own mental states that tells us the inner nature of the matter that makes up the brain.  It seemed to me that Hayek’s position amounted to something like functionalism in reverse:  It’s not that the mind turns out to be a kind of causal network of the sort that might be instantiated in the brain, or a computer, or some other material system -- understood naively, i.e. taking our perceptual experience of these physical systems as accurate representations of their intrinsic nature.  Rather, introspection of our mental states and their relations is actually a kind of direct awareness of the inner nature of causation itself.  We shouldn’t reduce mind to causal relations; rather we should inflate our notion of causation and see in it the mental properties we know from introspection.

So I then argued, and wrote up the results both in the dissertation and in another article.  But the views were weird, required a great deal of abstractive effort even to understand, and one had to care about Hayek even to try, which almost no philosophers of mind do.  To be sure, Searle was interested in Hayek in a general way -- when Steven Postrel and I interviewed him for Reason, and when I talked to him about Hayek on other occasions, he even expressed interest in The Sensory Order in particular -- but this interest never manifested itself in his published work.  Chalmers very kindly gave me lots of feedback on the Hayekian spin on Russell that I was trying to develop, and pushed me to clarify the underlying metaphysics.  But his own tendency was, as I have said, to explore (at least tentatively) the panpsychist reading of Russell.

And yet my own development of Hayek might itself seem ultimately to have flirted with panpsychism.  For if introspection of our mental states gives us awareness of the inner nature of causation, doesn’t that imply that causation itself -- including causation in the world outside the brain -- is in some sense mental?  This certainly went beyond anything Hayek himself had said.  In my later thinking about Hayek’s position (of which I would give a more adequate exposition in my Cambridge Companion to Hayek article on Hayek’s philosophy of mind), I would retreat from this reading and emphasize instead the idea that introspection and perception give us only representations of the inner and outer worlds, and not their intrinsic nature.

This, for reasons I spell out in the article just referred to, offers a possible solution to the problem that qualia pose for naturalism.  But because the view presupposes the notion of representation, it does not account for intentionality.  Here my inclinations went in more of a “mysterian” direction.  I had long been fascinated by Colin McGinn’s arguments to the effect that there was a perfectly naturalistic explanation of consciousness, but one we may be incapable in principle of understanding given the limitations on our cognitive faculties.  I thought we could say more about consciousness than McGinn thought we probably could, but I also came to think that his mysterian approach was correct vis-à-vis the intentional content of our mental states.  Lockwood and Hayek said things that lent plausibility to this.  

I would later largely abandon the Hayekian position altogether, because it presupposes an indirect realist account of perception that I would eventually reject.  (That took some time.  The influence of indirect realism is clearly evident in my book Philosophy of Mind.)  But I had come to some conclusions in the philosophy of mind that would persist.  First, as Russell had argued, physics, which materialists take to be the gold standard of our knowledge of the material world, in fact doesn’t give us knowledge of the intrinsic nature of matter in the first place.  The usual materialist theories were not even clearly thought out, much less correct.  Second, a complete naturalistic explanation of intentionality is impossible.  

But I was still a naturalist.  It was also while still a naturalist that I first started to take a serious interest in Aristotelianism, though at the time that interest had to do with ethics rather than metaphysics.   Even before I became an atheist I had been introduced to the Aristotelian idea that what is good for us is determined by our nature, and that our nature is what it is whether or not we think of it as having come from God.  After becoming an atheist, then, I became drawn to ethicists like Philippa Foot, who defended a broadly Aristotelian approach to the subject from a secular point of view.  Her book Virtues and Vices and Alasdair MacIntyre’s After Virtue were the big influences on my thinking about ethical theory during my atheist years.  

One consequence of this was that I always took teleology seriously, because it was so clearly evident a feature of ordinary practical reasoning.  (How did I reconcile this with naturalism?  I’m not sure I then saw the conflict all that clearly.  But in any event I thought that teleological notions could be fitted into a naturalistic framework in the standard, broadly Darwinian way -- the function of a thing is to be cashed out in terms of the reason why it was selected, etc.  I only later came to see that teleology ultimately had to be a bottom level feature of the world rather than a derivative one.)

After Virtue also taught me another important lesson -- that a set of concepts could become hopelessly confused and lead to paradox when yanked from the original context which gave them their intelligibility.  MacIntyre argued that this is what had happened to the key concepts of modern moral theory, removed as they had been from the pre-modern framework that was their original home.  I would later come to see that the same thing is true in metaphysics -- that the metaphysical categories contemporary philosophers make casual use of (causation, substance, essence, mind, matter, and so forth) have been grotesquely distorted in modern philosophy, pulled as they have been from the classical (and especially Aristotelian-Scholastic) framework in which they had been so carefully refined.  As I argue in The Last Superstition, many of the so-called “traditional” problems of philosophy are really just artifacts of the anti-Scholastic revolution of the moderns.  They flow from highly contentious and historically contingent metaphysical assumptions, and do not reflect anything about the nature of philosophical reflection per se.  And the standard moves of modern atheist argumentation typically presuppose these same assumptions.  But I wouldn’t see that for years.

I was on my way to seeing it, however.  Several crucial background elements were in place by the late 90s.  Fregean and related arguments had gotten me to take very seriously the idea that something like Platonic realism might be true.  (I would later see that Aristotelian realism was in fact the right way to go, but the basic anti-naturalistic move had been made.)  The arguments of Searle and others had shown that existing versions of materialism were no good.  Russellian arguments had shown that modern science and philosophy had no clear idea of what matter was in the first place.  Whatever it was supposed to be, though, it seemed it was not something to which one could assimilate mind, at least not if one wanted to avoid panpsychism.  Naturalism came to seem mysterious at best.  Meanwhile, Aristotelian ideas had a certain plausibility.  All that was needed was some systematic alternative to naturalism.

Then, in the late 90s, while still a grad student, I was given an opportunity to teach a philosophy of religion course, followed by several opportunities to teach “intro to philosophy” courses.  In the latter, I wanted to focus on topics that would be of interest to undergrads who might have no general interest in philosophy.  Since everyone had some interest in religion (even if only, in some cases, a hostile interest), arguments for God’s existence seemed a good topic for at least part of the course.  Naturally, that was a topic for the philosophy of religion course too.  So, I had a reason to revisit the subject after having given it relatively little thought for many years.

At first I taught the material the way so many professors do: Here are the arguments; here are the obvious fallacies they commit; let’s move on.  I never came across like Richard Dawkins, but I no doubt did come across like Nigel Warburton (say): politely dismissive.  And, as I gradually came to see, totally ill-informed.  The “line ‘em up, then shoot ‘em down” approach was boring, and the arguments seemed obviously stupid.  Yet the people who had presented them historically were obviously not stupid.  So, it seemed to me that it would be interesting to try to give the arguments a run for their money, and to try to make it understandable to the students why anyone would ever have accepted them.

So I started to read and think more about them.  I came to find William Rowe’s approach to the Leibnizian sort of cosmological argument interesting and pedagogically useful.  He didn’t seem to accept the argument, but he made it clear that asking “What caused God?”, “How do we know the universe had a beginning?”, etc. weren’t really serious objections.  He also made it clear that the thrust of the argument had to do with what was a straightforward and undeniably serious philosophical question:  Should we regard the world as ultimately explicable or not?  If not, then the argument fails.  But if so, then it does seem to make it plausible that something like God, or at least the God of the philosophers, must exist.  And it didn’t seem silly to wonder whether there might be such an explanation.  Richard Taylor’s clear, punchy chapter on natural theology in his little book Metaphysics made the same point, and made for a useful selection for the students to read.  

Naturally, I had already long been aware of this sort of argument.  The difference was that when I had first thought about it years before I was approaching it as someone who had had a religious background and wanted to see whether there was any argument for God’s existence that was really persuasive.  Russell’s retort to Copleston, to the effect that we can always insist that the universe is just there and that’s that, had then seemed to me sufficient to show that the argument was simply not compelling.  We’re just not rationally forced to accept it.  I had, as it were, put the argument on trial and it had been unable to establish its innocence to my satisfaction.  But now I was approaching it as a naturalist who was trying to give my students a reason to see the argument as something at least worth thinking about for a class period or two.  I was playing defense attorney rather than prosecution, but a defense attorney with the confidence of someone who didn’t have a stake in his client’s acquittal.  Already being a confirmed naturalist, I could be dispassionate rather than argumentative, and could treat the whole thing as a philosophical exercise.  

And from that point of view it started to seem that Russell’s reply, while it had rhetorical power, was perhaps not quite airtight philosophically.  Sure, you could always say that there’s no ultimate explanation.  And maybe there’s no way to prove otherwise.  But is it really true?  Is it really even more plausible to think that than to think that there is an explanation?  Guys like Rowe and Taylor, by no means religious fanatics or apologists but just philosophers entertaining a deep question, seemed to take the question pretty seriously.  Interesting, I thought.  Though for the time being, “interesting” -- rather than correct or persuasive -- was all I found it.  

Then there was Aquinas.  At the high tide of my undergrad Brash Young Atheist stage, I had taken a class on medieval philosophy with the late John Cronquist, an atheist professor at Cal State Fullerton who was absolutely contemptuous of Christianity.  Campus apologists of the Protestant stripe were a frequent target of his ire, though he had a choice quip or two about Catholicism as well.  He was one of the smartest and most well-read people I have ever known -- the kind of guy you find intellectually intimidating and hope not to get in an argument with -- and I liked him very much.  One of the odd and interesting things about that course, though, was how respectfully Cronquist treated some of the medievals, especially Aquinas.  He said that compared to them, contemporary pop apologists were “like a pimple on the ass of an athlete.”  (I remember him dramatically pointing to his own posterior as he said this, for emphasis.)  He obviously didn’t buy the Scholastic system for a moment, but he treated the material as worth taking a semester to try to understand.  And he said a couple of things that stood out.  First, for reasons I don’t recall him elaborating on much, he seemed to think that the Third Way in particular might have something to be said for it.  Second, he said that the mind-body problem, which he seemed to think was terribly vexing, really boiled down to the problem of universals.  For years I would wonder what he meant by that.  (I now think it must have had to do with the way our grasp of abstract concepts features in Aristotelian arguments for the immateriality of the intellect.) 

At the time I filed these remarks away as curiosities (just as I had then regarded the material we covered in the class as mere curiosities).  But I think his example made it easier for me, years later, to take a second look at Aquinas as I prepared course material.  I look back at my first lectures on the Five Ways with extreme embarrassment.  If you’d heard them, you’d have thought I was cribbing from an advance copy of The God Delusion, if not in tone then at least in the substance of my criticisms.  But that started slowly to change as I read more about the arguments and began to work the material into my lectures.  A good friend of mine, who had also gone from Catholicism to atheism and was a fellow grad student, was familiar with William Lane Craig’s book The Cosmological Argument from Plato to Leibniz, and seemed to find it useful in preparing his own lectures on the subject.  Our discussions of the arguments were very helpful.  Furthermore, Atheism and Theism by J. J. C. Smart and John Haldane had recently appeared, with Haldane defending, and Smart treating respectfully, some old-fashioned Thomistic arguments for the existence of God.  Such materials opened up a new world.  The way I and so many other philosophers tended to read the Five Ways was, as I gradually came to realize, laughably off base.  

The immediate effect was that I found a way to teach the Five Ways without seeming like I was putting fish in a barrel for the students to shoot at.  I still didn’t agree with the arguments, but at least teaching them was getting interesting.  I recall one class period when, having done my best to try to defend some argument (the First Way, I think) against various objections, I finally stated whatever it was I thought at the time was a difficulty that hadn’t been satisfactorily answered.  One of my smartest students expressed relief: She had been worried for a moment that there might be a good argument for God’s existence after all!  (Anyone who thinks wishful thinking is all on the side of religious people is fooling himself.)  

None of this undermined my commitment to naturalism for some time.  I published my first several journal articles while still in grad school, and two of them were criticisms of the doctrine of the Trinity.  (I’m now a staunch Trinitarian, of course.  But once again, it turns out that I still more or less agree with the arguments I then presented.  The versions of Trinitarianism I then attacked are, I continue to think, wrong.  But Trinitarianism itself is true.)  

But the language of act and potency, per se and per accidens causal series and the like started to enter my lectures on Aquinas, and before long, my thinking.  It was all very strange.  Aquinas’s arguments had a certain power when all of this metaphysical background was taken account of.  And there was a certain plausibility to the metaphysics.  There were reasons for distinguishing between actuality and potentiality, the different kinds of causal series, and so forth.   Yet no one seemed to talk that way anymore -- or, again, at least no one “mainstream.”  Could there really be anything to it all if contemporary philosophers weren’t saying anything about it?  And yet, precisely because they weren’t talking about it, they weren’t refuting it either.  Indeed, when they did say anything about Aquinas’s arguments at all, most of them showed only that they couldn’t even be bothered to get him right, much less show why he was mistaken.  Arguments from current philosophical fashion are bad enough.  But when most philosophers not only do not accept a certain view, but demonstrate that they don’t even understand what it is, things can start to smell very fishy indeed.

And so they did.  I already knew from the lay of the land in the philosophy of language and philosophy of mind that the standard naturalist approaches had no solid intellectual foundation, and themselves rested as much on fashion as on anything else.  Even writers like Searle, who I admired greatly and whose naturalism I shared, had no plausible positive alternative.  McGinn-style mysterianism started to seem like a dodge, especially given that certain arguments (like the Platonic realist ones) seemed to show that matter simply is not in fact all that there is, not merely that we can’t know how it can be all that there is.  Some secular writers were even toying with Aristotelian ideas anyway.  The only reason for not taking Aquinas and similar thinkers seriously seemed to be that most other academic philosophers weren’t taking them seriously.  And yet as I had come to learn, many of them didn’t even understand Aquinas and Co. in the first place, and their own naturalism was riddled with problems.  Against Aquinas, for naturalism -- the case increasingly seemed to come down to the consensus of the profession.  And what exactly was that worth?  

It isn’t worth a damn thing, of course.  Careerists might not see that, nor might a young man more excited by the “question what your parents taught you” side of philosophy than all that “objective pursuit of truth” stuff.  But a grownup will see it, and a philosopher had sure as hell better see it.  

I don’t know exactly when everything clicked.  There was no single event, but a gradual transformation.  As I taught and thought about the arguments for God’s existence, and in particular the cosmological argument, I went from thinking “These arguments are no good” to thinking “These arguments are a little better than they are given credit for” and then to “These arguments are actually kind of interesting.”  Eventually it hit me: “Oh my goodness, these arguments are right after all!”  By the summer of 2001 I would find myself trying to argue my wife’s skeptical physicist brother-in-law into philosophical theism on the train the four of us were taking through eastern Europe.

There’s more to the story than that, of course.  In particular, it would take an essay of its own to explain why I returned to the Catholic Church, specifically, as I would by the end of 2001.  But I can already hear some readers protesting at what I have said.  I don’t mean the New Atheist types, always on the hunt for some ad hominem nugget that will excuse them from having to take the actual arguments of the other side seriously.  (God Himself could come down from on high and put before such people an airtight ontological proof of His existence while parting the Red Sea, and they’d still insist that what really motivated these arguments was a desire to rationalize His moral prejudices.  And that their own continued disbelief was just a matter of, you know, following the evidence where it leads.)  

No, I’m talking about a certain kind of religious believer, the type who’s always going on about how faith is really a matter of the heart rather than the head, that no one’s ever been argued into religion, etc.  It will be said by such a believer that my change of view was too rationalistic, too cerebral, too bloodless, too focused on a theoretical knowledge of the God of the philosophers rather than a personal response to the God of Abraham, Isaac, and Jacob.

But the dichotomy is a false one, and the implied conception of the relationship between faith and reason not only foolish but heterodox.  As to the heterodoxy and foolishness of fideism, and the correct understanding of the relationship of faith and reason, I have addressed that set of issues in a previous post.  As to the “heart versus head” stuff, it seems to me to rest on an erroneous bifurcation of human nature.  Man is a unity, his rationality and animality, intellect and passions, theoretical and moral lives all ultimately oriented toward the same end.  That is why even a pagan like Aristotle knew that our happiness lay in “the contemplation and service of God,” whose existence he knew of via philosophical argumentation.  That is why Plotinus could know that we “forget the father, God” because of “self-will.”  While the pagan may have no access to the supernatural end that only grace makes possible, he is still capable of a natural knowledge of God, and will naturally tend to love what he knows.  

As Plotinus’s remark indicates, that does not mean that the will does not have a role to play.  But that is true wherever reason leads us to a conclusion we might not like, not merely in matters of religion.  And once you have allowed yourself to see the truth that reason leads you to, what reason apprehends is (given the convertibility of the transcendentals) as good and beautiful as it is real.  If you find yourself intellectually convinced that there is a divine Uncaused Cause who sustains the world and you in being at every instant, and don’t find this conclusion extremely strange and moving, something that leads you to a kind of reverence, then I daresay you haven’t understood it.  Of course, there are those whose heads and hearts are so out of sync that they cannot follow both at the same time.  But we shouldn’t mistake this pathology for an insight into human nature.

Speaking for myself, anyway, I can say this much.  When I was an undergrad I came across the saying that learning a little philosophy leads you away from God, but learning a lot of philosophy leads you back.  As a young man who had learned a little philosophy, I scoffed.  But in later years and at least in my own case, I would come to see that it’s true.

sábado, 21 de julho de 2012

El matrimonio homosexual dispara el número de vientres de alquiler en los países pobres


El 26 de mayo, un reportaje de The Telegraph reveló que en el último año habían tenido lugar en la India 2000 nacimientos por vientre de alquiler, de los cuales la mitad (1000) provenían de "clientes" británicos. En el Reino Unidos, sin embargo, sólo tuvieron lugar 100 nacimientos.

El negocio de los vientres de alquiler se está moviendo aceleradamente hacia el Tercer Mundo. Supone un negocio de más de 200.000 millones de euros al año, y se basa en la diferencia de precio que cobran las madres: hacerlo en países pobres cuesta hasta una quinta parte que en Occidente. Algo que unos ven como una forma de explotación, y otros como una forma de ganar un dinero que sería imposible conseguir de otra manera.

Incremento de demandas de parejas gay
Cada vez es mayor además el número de reclamaciones que llegan de parejas homosexuales. Según el citado artículo, en la clínica The Birthplace of Joy, de Nueva Delhi, por ejemplo, el 100% de los clientes son extranjeros, y la mitad de ellos parejas homosexuales que acuden para realizar la operación de fecundación.

El experto en bioética Michael Cook, director de BioEdge, dio un paso más adelante para investigar esta cuestión. Y se dirigió a diversas clínicas de la India que ofrecen este servicio para preguntarles si esperan un auge de peticiones si en algunos países (como Francia) se legaliza el matrimonio homosexual.

"Absolutamente, sí", fue la contundente respuesta de la doctora Samundi Sankari, del Shrusti Fertility Research Center de Chennai, que cada vez recibe más demandas de Estados Unidos e Israel para todo lo que tiene que ver con tratamiento de la fertilidad. Y añadió: "La principal razón por la que los clientes vienen desde fuera de la India es el excelente cuidado personal, la experiencia y el ahorro. Los costes que pagan son una quinta parte de los que pagan por alquilar un vientre en Estados Unidos y Europa".

Por su parte, el doctor Samit Sekhar, del Kiran Infertility Centre, en Hyderabad, confiesa: "Tenemos un número considerable de personas gay que visitan nuestra clínica para utlizar los servicios de un óvulo donante". Y, lo que es más relevante: "Hemos visto un incremento en el número de parejas gay y hombres solos que vienen a nuestra clínica a medida que su unión pública va siendo legitimada en sus respectivos países".

Esto lo corroboran incluso clínicas norteamericanas. El doctor Jeffrey Steinberg, director de dos institutos de fertilidad en Los Ángeles y Las Vegas, lo ha estudiado y se lo explica a Cooke: "Cuando un país empieza a considerar la legalización del matrimonio gay, tenemos un incremento de consultas sobre lo que implica contratar un óvulo donante y el vientre de alquiler. Una tercera parte de las consultas siguen adelante con nuestros servicios incluso antes de que se apruebe la ley. Otro tercio nos dicen que esperarán a ver cómo se desarrolla la legislación. Y del otro tercio no volvemos a saber nada". Pero una vez legalizado el matrimonio homosexua, "un 40% firman enseguida".

Impresionante reportaje
Un reciente reportaje televisivo de The Wall Street Journal (puede verse más abajo) describía con toda crudeza estos procesos, relatando el caso de dos gays, Jocelyn -que será el padre biológico- y su compañero, que alquilan a una madre en la India: "Trato de estar tranquilo en un proceso que parece surrealista", admite Jocelyn.

Los médicos, afirma con toda frialdad el doctor Sekhar ante la cámara, no le dicen a la madre que su hijo irá con una pareja homosexual: "No lo entenderían, es un concepto extraño entre gente sin educación".

Y es que, obviamente, las mujeres que se someten a este proceso son extremadamente pobres, e incluso recurren a alquilar su útero y tener un hijo al que no volverán a ver, para alimentar a otros. Pero quitarle el niño a su madre no roba el sueño a los contratistas. Incluso en ocasiones los niños han quedado en un vacío legal, al no ser reconocida su nacionalidad en los países de origen de los clientes (homosexuales o heterosexuales).

A favor y en contra
Expertos en bioética recuerdan que las mujeres en la India no tienen la misma capacidad de decisión en Occidente, y por tanto es imposible saber si ofrecerse como vientre de alquiler es una idea suya o una exigencia de su marido por razones económicas.

Pero los dirigentes del negocio no lo ven de la misma forma. La doctora Nayna Patel, directora médica de la clínica Akanksha, dice que ha visto "cómo vivían antes y cómo viven ahora" las madres de alquiler, en referencia al dinero que cobran: "Ha cambiado sus vidas. Es muy transformador", elogia.

En la investigación de Michael Cook hubo una voz discrepante en torno a la influencia de la legalización del matrimonio homosexual. El doctor Shivani Sachdev, del Surrogate Center India, no cree que eso aumente el número de demandas: "Apoyaremos que el matrimonio entre personas del mismo sexo se apruebe en cualquier país, pero no creo que eso incremente nuestra clientela". La mitad de ella, sin embargo -desvela BioEdge-, son parejas gays

Pinche aquí para ver el extraordinariamente revelador reportaje de la televisión de The Wall Street Journal sobre esta práctica. Está en inglés, con subtítulos en español.

Rally Spotlights Persecution Against Christians - Groups Show Support to Thousands Dying for Their Faith Today

By Edward Pentin

ROME, JULY 19, 2012 (Zenit.org).- Fervent calls for governments to condemn acts of persecution against Christians; a plea to open the beatification process of the assassinated Christian Pakistani minister Shahbaz Bhatti; and demands that Christians suffering persecution be granted full refugee status.

Just some of the appeals passionately delivered at a rally on behalf of persecuted Christians, which appropriately took place in Piazza dei Santi Apostoli in the center of Rome on Wednesday. 

Called "Salviamo i Cristiani" -- Save the Christians -- and organized by an association of Italian Catholic and pro-life groups, the demonstration was held to raise awareness, express solidarity, and call for action on behalf of the many Christians suffering persecution in the world today. 

The association highlighted that, globally, no other group is more persecuted: Out of every 100 people who suffer violations to their right to religious freedom, 75 are Christians. It added that during the course of history, an estimated 70 million Christians have been martyred for their faith, including 40 million in the 20th century alone. Each year, it said there are 105,000 new Christian martyrs killed by Islamic terrorists, Hindu extremists in India, or Communists in China, North Korea and Vietnam.

"We're told about a triumph of democracy and peace," said historian Roberto de Mattei of the Lepanto Foundation, a non-profit organization defending the principles and institutions of Western Christian civilization. "After Sept. 11, they said don't worry, because the politics of dialogue and interreligious peace will prevail. Today, we're told about the health of the Magreb, that it is a model of the Arab Spring, showing hope and promise."

"But the reality of what is before our eyes is tragically different," De Mattei said. "Today, we are here to cry out our indignation, and launch our appeal for persecuted Christians." 

The Italian historian recalled that last month, the Church announced it would beatify Don Pino Piglisi, a priest killed by the Mafia in 1993, as a martyr -- as someone who had died "in hated of the faith." 

"Everyone rightly condemns the Mafia as radically evil, but no one, or few people, attributes such evil to the fanatics of Allah who kill Christians in hatred of the faith," he said. The professor then called on the Church to officially open the process of beatification for Shahbaz Bhatti, the Catholic Pakistani minister for minorities, who was killed by an Islamic extremist March 2, 2011. 

"If we recognize Don Pino Puglisi, it is much more important to announce the beatification process of Shahbaz Bhatti, killed by a Muslim terrorist," De Mattei told ZENIT, noting that the killers were the Taliban "who said they killed in name of the Koran." By opening the process, he said Bhatti could become "a model and patron for all Christians persecuted in Muslim countries."

The well-known Italian-Egyptian convert from Islam, Magdi Cristiano Allam, called on governments, and the Italian authorities in particular to propose that Christians persecuted for their religious belief be awarded refugee status. Current Italian law, Allam and others argue, is insufficient in assisting Christians fleeing violent persecution, notably those living in some Muslim-majority states, or nations where Sharia law is practiced. 

Speaking to ZENIT, Allam said the rally was important as a "testimony of our support for persecuted, discriminated and massacred Christians," adding that "we want to defend the non-negotiable values of life, the dignity of the person, religious freedom."

Why so silent?

Asked why governments tend to ignore the plight of persecuted Christians worldwide, he answered: "Because they are afraid, because of economic interests, because this is a West that puts money, material things, at the center." He also said they are "afraid to show any rigor towards Islam when it comes to the fundamental respect for the rights of the person" -- an approach that "can have a negative impact on Christians that live in those countries."

Allam, who was received into the Catholic Church by Pope Benedict XVI in 2008 and is now a Member of the European Parliament, noted that around the end of the 7th century, 95% of the populations on the southern and eastern shores of the Mediterranean were Christian; today there are just 12 million, representing 6% of the population. That figure is expected to halve by 2020. "Only if we are strong and certain of our roots, faith, and values can we be respected," he said. 

The journalist and politician also had some harsh criticism for U.S. President Barack Obama and his approach to Islam. "Obama has played a fundamental role in the legitimization of radical Islam," he said. 

Asked about the Obama administration's threats to religious liberty of U.S. Catholics, Allam said: "Obama is undoubtedly an expression of relativism, as we have seen recently in his support for same-sex 'marriage,' his support for abortion," he said. "Obama is a person who puts money at the center, who wants to support the great financial organizations. He is a person who wants nothing to do with anyone who puts the person at the center -- the natural family, local communities, values, rules for the common good. Obama represents a danger for our civilization."

Benjamin Harnwell, founder of the Rome-based Dignitatis Humanae Institute, stressed that what makes persecution against Christians unique is the supernatural basis of the persecution -- adding that Jesus warned that Christians should expect to be persecuted as a counter-cultural sign to the world. 

"Jesus said no servant is greater than his master, if they persecuted me they'll persecute you," he said. "There's a warning in that injunction to his followers to expect to be persecuted -- it's the light that is Jesus Christ that shines through those who bear witness to him -- the light that the darkness did not comprehend, and still does not comprehend to this day."

De Mattei agreed that persecution is the natural environment for Christians, but also that it should be confronted. "The Church has lived with persecution since its origins, also during communism, but the persecutors are bad," he said. "We have to resist, to fight."

Ignorance is bliss

Remarkably, in a city that's home to Catholicism and with many monuments to martyrs who died in hatred of the faith over the centuries, the rally only drew about 300 people. Praising the Holy Father's enthusiasm toward a New Evangelization in the West, Harnwell said he hopes it "will in practice mean something more than constructing monuments to the prophets whom our forefathers stoned." The saints, he added, "are great when they're dead because we can say nice things about them, but when they're being persecuted in our time, we don't want to know." Furthermore, he said saints and martyrs of today provoke an "unforced solidarity," and show "the flame of faith that we need back."

Rome's mayor, Gianni Alemanno, gave a spirited speech in which he said the rally was of "extraordinary importance." He lamented that religious freedom is too often placed on the second tier of priorities, behind civil and political rights, and that the world must be made aware of the persecution of Christians. He also stressed the importance of reciprocity as the basis of relations, and called for "respect for our Christian identity and our integrity as Christians throughout the world." 

De Mattei described Wednesday's event as of "symbolic importance." If there were no such protests, he said "it would be a scandal."

sexta-feira, 20 de julho de 2012

Masacre de Cristianos en Nigeria, además del diálogo interreligioso, es necesaria la protección - Entrevista al profesor Introvigne

Por H. Sergio Mora

ROMA, viernes 20 julio 2012 (ZENIT.org).- En Nigeria cada domingo quien va a misa no sabe si retornará a su casa. Un país en el cual un reciente sondeo ha indicado que el 70% de la población considera que el diálogo interreligioso es la única salida del problema y por lo tanto rechaza la violencia de los fanáticos.

Para salir de la actual situación son necesarios varios factores: es fundamental el diálogo interreligioso, el adiestramiento de las fuerzas de la policía y del orden, el apoyo en la medida de lo posible a los sectores políticos islámicos no fanáticos, sin excluir la posibilidad de golpear las zonas francas que sirven, como las islas Tortugas, a los piratas.

Lo indicó en la entrevista a ZENIT que les proponemos a continuación, el profesor Massimo Introvigne, sociólogo e historiador, que participó este jueves 19 de julio en la Asociación de la Prensa Extranjera en Roma, junto al ministro de Exteriores de Italia, Giulio Terzi y otras autoridades, en el debate sobre la masacre de los cristianos en Nigeria, promovido por el Observatorio de la Libertad Religiosa del Ministerio de Exteriores de Italia.

¿Cuál es la función del Observatorio de la libertad religiosa?

–Prof. Introvigne: El Observatorio de la Libertad Religiosa, tiene funciones de coordinar iniciativas en diversos niveles.
En primer lugar, debe insistir ante las organizaciones internacionales para que se muevan. Aquí entra la insistencia metódica de la diplomacia italiana para que el problema de los cristianos en Nigeria entre en todas las iniciativas de paz y desarrollo, desde las Naciones Unidas a la Unión Europea.

Los tiempos de las organizaciones internacionales entretanto son siempre largos.

–Prof. Introvigne: De hecho como segundo punto está la colaboración bilateral. Italia ha desarrollado buenos sistemas de seguridad y vigilancia de objetivos sensibles. Ahora en Nigeria lamentablemente entre los objetivos sensibles están las Iglesias cristianas, por lo que ya existen programas para dar formación a los funcionarios administrativos, de las fuerzas del orden, de la policía y guardias de frontera nigerianas.

Por lo tanto sirve el diálogo y la seguridad. ¿Y qué más? 

–Prof. Introvigne: El tercer factor es dar apoyo a la política local en la medida de lo posible. Me explico mejor: si bien el diálogo interreligioso es tarea sobre todo de las instituciones religiosas –y sobre esto la Iglesia católica nos da ejemplo de coraje– el diálogo es la verdadera solución al problema. Por lo tanto debe incluir a personas que son referentes del islam político, excluyendo claramente a quienes son violentos o terroristas. A quienes como un dirigente del grupo armado Boko Haram en Nigeria, declaró que para los cristianos hay solamente tres alternativas: morir, convertirse al islam o emigrar. Estos sujetos tienen que ser excluidos del diálogo si bien algunas de las fuerzas del islam político podrían entrar en el mismo.

¿Hay algún otro punto importante?

–Prof. Introvigne: Sí, un cuarto factor es la regionalización del conflicto que es continental, y ve la presencia importante de focos de terrorismo en lugares fuera del control del Estado. Como la mitad de Somalia y el norte de Malí. En los últimos días, tuvimos pruebas de la presencia del Boko Haram nigeriano en la región de Gao, en Malí y en zonas controladas sustancialmente por Al Qaeda, donde van para abastecerse de armas y combustibles.

En este caso el diálogo y la policía pueden hacer poco.

–Prof. Introvigne: Y aquí hay un problema que es necesario resolver incluyendo todas las opciones, incluso la militar que entretanto requiere cautela. Por el momento el Consejo de Seguridad de las Naciones Unidas no las autoriza hasta que no sea claro qué tipo de iniciativas militares emplear de las que propone la Comunidad Económica de África oriental (EAC).

Existen países que ven las cosas de otra manera, como Burkina Faso, que querría extender el diálogo también a una de las formaciones fundamentalistas islámicas, mientras Nigeria no lo quiere.

¿Opciones militares que en algunos casos no se excluyen?

–Prof. Introvigne: La opción militar en el caso de Malí no puede ser excluida pues encontramos un territorio que funciona un poco como las islas Tortugas para los piratas. Quien quiera va y abre un cuartel para las armas y el adoctrinamiento.

No por casualidad Nigeria dijo que si hay intervención militar pondría a disposición sus tropas.

¿Cómo evitar la agresión a los cristianos?

–Prof. Introvigne: El diálogo es una de las dos piernas con la que camina la lucha a la persecución de los cristianos. Y es la que tiene más horizonte y decisiva, entretanto visto que cada domingo los cristianos siguen muriendo es necesaria también una intervención de tipo policial.

Italia está ayudando a la formación de las fuerzas del orden?

–Prof. Introvigne: Sí, como iniciativa de carácter bilateral, porque Italia cree que no se deba pasar encima del gobierno nigeriano, que es democrático y amigo, en donde el presidente es cristiano. No es el gobierno quien favorece estas violencia y es víctima de las mismas, entretanto el problema tiene centrales fuera de Nigeria.

¿Existe en Nigeria una mayoría silenciosa que no quiere la violencia?

–Prof. Introvigne: Sí, y querría el diálogo interreligioso. Una encuesta reciente en Nigeria indica que el 70% de la población propone el diálogo interreligioso como la salida del problema. Incluso si no hace noticia y nadie habla de esto.