The scene is from C. S. Lewis’s That Hideous Strength. The
callow young sociology professor, Mark Studdock, an atheist and a
social climber, has been detained in a cubicle deliberately fashioned
with odd annoying angles and not-quite-right pictures on the wall. His
detainers aim to break down in him any last sense of the inner harmony
between beauty and the moral good, or even between ordinary
presentability and decency. The fight is for the man’s soul.
His instructor presents him with a crucifix and asks him to tread
upon it. It’s a meaningless act, he says. It isn’t a man, only a cheap
piece of carved wood. There is no moral import to it. But something
in the young man recoils. He does not believe there was anything
special about Jesus. As far as he knows, Jesus was only a man condemned
to a shameful death by his enemies, on a trumped-up political charge.
And all of Jesus’ friends abandoned him on Calvary, and all of the
intellectual people that matter to him in England have long abandoned
him too. But for that very reason, to tread upon the crucifix seems
base. Why add that last small act of shaming to all the rest? The
still small voice speaks to him, saying, “This would be foul, petty,
ignoble. You must not do this.” If he complies, as far as he
knows, his career is made. If he refuses, his career is shot. He’s a
married man, and he’s ambitious, and he needs the money. It’s only a
piece of wood. The meaning of his life hangs in the balance. Nor can
we ever be sure that a man who betrays so clear a prohibition issued by
his conscience will be given that choice again, to undo the evil.
He refuses.
These days in our political and even ecclesiastical battles we hear a
great deal about the primacy of the conscience, but almost nothing
about what the conscience is and why we should care, not about our own
conscience, but about someone else’s. Robert George, in his new book Conscience and Its Enemies: Confronting the Dogmas of Liberal Secularism (ISI
Books), aims to supply the lack. He reminds us that conscience is, to
use Newman’s words, a “stern monitor,” not, as David Hume asserts, much
to the comfort of adolescents everywhere, the ratiocinative faculty by
which we construct “justifications” for what we wanted to do (or to get
out of doing) in the first place. Rather, the conscience warns us of
what we must do and of what we must not do. “The duty to
follow conscience,” George writes, “is a duty to do things or refrain
from doing things not because one wants to follow one’s duty but even if
one strongly does not want to follow it. The right of
conscience is a right to do what one judges oneself to be under
obligation to do, whether one welcomes the obligation or must overcome
strong aversion to fulfill it.”
In other words, as George notes, conscience is not a “permissions
department.” It commands and proscribes; and that’s why we spend so
much effort trying to circumvent it, muddle it, or stifle it
altogether. Mark Twain gives us a humorous instance of it when Huck
Finn must decide whether to rat on the runaway slave Jim or to protect
him. Huck “knows,” in an exterior way, from common chatter, that the
“right” thing to do would be to betray his friend and profit by it, but
something deep inside him tells him no, and so he too refuses, even
though he figures that he’ll probably end up in hell for it.
When someone says, “I may do this, because my conscience doesn’t
forbid me,” he is treating an absence as a presence. He feels no
command or proscription, and transmutes that insensibility into a proof
that what he wants is permissible. But that doesn’t follow. It may be
morally permissible; it may be downright virtuous; but it may be
wicked. Many an SS officer’s conscience was comfortably silent on the
issue of slaughtering Jews. People steeped in evil may even hug
themselves for the benefits their evil confers upon mankind. So it is
that snuffing out the lives of unborn children, in the minds of some, is
more than permissible: it is a great and glorious good, to be
celebrated with cake and icing. Conscience can be unformed or deformed;
conscience does not determine what is good or evil, but must hearken to
the truth of the matter, even if the person cannot articulate just why
he must do what he would prefer to leave undone, or why he must not do
what he would dearly like to do.
We are not obliged to respect a man’s permission slips. We are not
obliged to throw the hedonist his party. We are not obliged to buy the
adolescent’s toys, or even to stock our shelves with them. Indeed, when
someone asserts that he ought to be allowed to do something because he
wants to do it, and because he doesn’t hear the voice of conscience
warning against it—he wants to use cocaine, he and his enemy want to
engage in a duel, he likes pornography—we needn’t give much standing to
his feelings. His permission slip puts the matter on the table,
that’s all. We need to ask about the nature of what he wants, whether
it is indeed morally neutral, or virtuous, or vicious, whether allowing
it conduces to the common good. But it is a different matter entirely
when that man’s monitor does speak, “Thou shalt!” and “Thou shalt not!”
Why is that? Is it because then his preferences or repugnancies are
especially strong? Your dog may have a strong desire to snitch food
from a guest’s plate, but we aren’t overriding his conscience when we
keep him from doing it. He may have a strong aversion against going
outside in the pouring rain to do his business, but we aren’t shackling
his moral sensibility when we make him go out anyway. That’s because
the dog is not a moral agent. He does not apprehend the good and
internalize it, making it his own, allowing it to inform his choices, to
build his personality. We might say that he knows “rules” but not law.
But man is a moral agent. That isn’t just something accidental to
man, as for instance that he has five fingers on a hand and not six. It
is essential to his being. It isn’t just Christians who believe that.
All the great pagans did also. It’s why the poet Hesiod says that the
Muses, daughters of Zeus, grant to the man they favor the wisdom to
craft straight judgments—we might say beautiful judgments, right
verdicts—and the eloquence to persuade others of their rightness.
To forbid someone to do what his conscience commands him to do, or,
worse still, to compel him to do what his conscience instructs him he
must not do, is thus to work violence upon him at the core of his
being. It is not the same as when we restrain people from the evils
that their consciences, dormant, silent, do not tell them they must not
do, or when, more rarely and with a heavier burden of justification upon
us, we compel them to do something which their consciences do not tell
them they must do. For then we are not violating an express decree of
the conscience; we are supplying the lack of one. We may even, but most
rarely and with an extraordinarily heavy burden of justification,
overrule another man’s conscience, not by compelling him, but by taking
the reins ourselves and doing what he will not do; that’s the case when
we give blood transfusions to infants in imminent danger of death, over the wishes of parents who object.
But no man has the right to require another to be less than a man, to
demote him to the status of a non-moral agent, like a beast, or a cog
in a machine. No man may steal my humanity, by demanding treason
against that stern monitor, my conscience. But this is exactly what is
happening before our eyes, in what used to be a free country. We are
demanding obeisance to and participation in things that until eleven
o’clock last night almost everyone (and all Christians and observant
Jews) believed to be evil, and believed it with strong reasons
prescinding from the nature of man and from revelation.
The “enemies of conscience,” as Professor George calls them,
simultaneously and incoherently deny the existence of moral truths that
bind the conscience—other people’s consciences, while they reserve for
themselves a moral right to bind and loose those other people,
mechanically, pragmatically, to bring about some vague ideal society.
In such a world, everyone is a god or an ant, but not a man. More to
follow.